In my efforts to articulate what makes history distinct from other disciplines I have started reading some older literature on the philosophy of history. Although this literature is no longer in vogue, it might still be relevant in distinguishing history from non-history. I am focusing on historical methods and practices because I think these will prove the most useful in identifying what is unique about history.
I think it is clear that unlike some disciplines, history has no unique content. Numerous disciplines turn to the past, or more properly, the artifacts thought to have been created in that past and use those artifacts today. The content cannot uniquely demarcate the boundaries of history. But there does seem to be a set of practices or a method that separates history from other efforts to use the past.
R. G. Collingwood’s The Idea of History offers some points that merit further reflection, particularly on the importance of asking questions in order to recover the problem some historical actor was trying to solve. We can only begin to understand what a historical actor was doing if we understand the problem that actor was trying to solve. This seems, to me, a useful starting point. Collingwood has shifted our focus from our present-centered ideas to the historical actor’s understanding and meaning. Historical understanding and meaning are at the heart of his question-and-answer approach, which he most succinctly presents in his An Autobiography. In The Idea of History Collingwood turns his attention to understanding and meaning in a section on historical evidence.
Collingwood is railing against the “scissors and paste” historians. Such historians, he claims, first “decide what we want to know about and then go in search of statements about it, oral or written, purporting to be made by actors in the events concerned,” or made by reliable witnesses (p. 257). “History constructed by excerpting and combining the testimonies of different authorities I call scissors-and-paste history” (p. 251). The problem, as Collingwood sees it, is the historians who practice such history fail to ask why a particular statement was made at the time and take it as self evident that the statement relates to the historians’ own ideas. These historians are also forced, when confronted with conflicting testimonies, to decide which is correct and should be included and which is false and can safely be excluded. Here again such historians are imposing their own categories and standards of correct or incorrect rather than understanding what the historical actors might have meant, that is, what problems the historical actors were trying to solve.
A closely related problem arises because the scissors-and-paste historians always wants more testimony:
So, however much testimony he has, his zeal as an historian makes him want more. But if he has a large amount of testimony, it becomes so difficult to manipulate and work up into a convincing narrative that , speaking as a mere weak mortal, he wishes he had less.
Consciousness of the dilemma has often driven men into scepticism [sic] about the very possibility of historical knowledge. And quite rightly, if knowledge means scientific knowledge and history means scissors-and-paste history. Scissors-and-paste historians who brush the dilemma aside with the blessed word ‘hypercriticism’ are only confessing that in their own professional practice they do not find that it troubles them, because they work to such a low standard of scientific cogency that their consciences become anaesthetized [sic]. Such cases in contemporary life are highly interesting, because in the history of science one often meets with them and wonders how such extraordinary blindness was possible. The answer is that people who exhibit it have committed themselves to an impossible task, in this case the task of scissors-and-paste history, and since for practical reasons they cannot back out of it they have to blind themselves to its impossibility. The scissors-and-paste historian protects himself from seeing the truth about his own methods by carefully choosing subjects which he is able to ‘get away’ with, exactly as the nineteenth-century landscape-painter protected himself from seeing that his theory of landscape was all wrong by choosing what he called paintable subjects. The subjects must be those about which a certain amount of testimony is accessible, not too little and not too much; not so uniform as to give the historian nothing to do, not so divergent as to baffle his endeavours to do it. Practiced on these principles, history was at worst a parlour game, and at best an elegant accomplishment (my emphasis; p. 279).
The problem seems to be that scissors-and-paste historians allow their own ideas and convictions to drive their search for testimony, which when confronted with a surfeit of seemingly relevant testimony they then prune according to their own prejudices. Their search begins and ends with the statements themselves. Scissor-and-paste historians then string these bits of testimony together in a narrative. In the end, such history is merely a “parlour game,” a sort of textual hide-and-seek.
The proper historian, Collingwood argues, uses the existence of the statement as the starting point, as the opportunity to formulate a series of questions about that statement: why the historical actor made it; what the historical actor could have meant by it; what does it reveal about the historical actor’s understanding of the world, of the political situation, of the social context; etc. It is this “questioning activity which is the dominant factor in history” (p. 273). There are two important facets to this questioning activity:
- Every step in the research process requires asking a new question. These questions are not random nor haphazardly arranged. They must be asked in the right order.
- These questions must be formulated by the historian who must search for evidence to answer them in the historical record.
- In looking for evidence to answer these questions, the historian must look beyond testimony and treat everything as possible evidence.
Collingwood is trying to distinguish good from bad history. He was hopeful that scissors-and-paste history had fallen out of fashion by the 1930s, but I am not so sanguine. In fact, it seems that in our world where people have increasing access to the remnants of the past, scissors-and-paste history is once again a problem. Further, I don’t think scissors-and-paste history has ever completely fallen out of fashion in much non-academic history of science. Certainly, all the “father-of-x” or the “making-of-the-modern-y” histories are typically scissors-and-paste histories (for a nice rejection of the “father-of-x” form, see Unsound history and earlier Lisa commits the ‘father of’ sin). The pitfalls of scissors-and-paste history also seems to be at the heart of Helen King’s critique of Don Shelton’s article (see History and the Problem of Historical Expertise).
I agree with Collingwood: good history begins by seeking to understand what the historical actors meant. And to do that, we have to begin by seeing their products—statements, texts, letters, instruments, buildings, etc—as the solutions to problems they were trying to solve. Our problems were not their problems.
6 replies on “R. G. Collingwood on Historical Practice”
Thanks for this very interesting contribution – reading your comments on Collingwood was very helpful, and reminded me of teaching him in a course on historical methods some years ago! I agree that he is neglected today, and that this is a pity when he often raises questions about our underlying assumptions on method. I particularly like his image of ‘interrogating’ the sources – I asked my students to imagine getting the source in a corner of the room and not letting it go until it answers! He is also really good on the sheer range of what could potentially count as a ‘source’.
Thanks for the comments. I too think we wrongly neglect Collingwood. Like you I find him useful in thinking about sources—what constitutes sources and how to interpret or understand those sources.
I am rereading parts of his An Autobiography now in preparation for a reading group this week. In both works I appreciate how he shifts the focus from our assumptions to the historical actor’s meaning. Propositions cease to have meaning in themselves but rather only as the answer to a very specific question articulated by the historical actor. It seems to me that if you take Collingwood seriously, you can’t wander off in search of terms that then string together into a story, for each instance of those terms quite likely meant something different for the actors who used them.
[…] in our modern world often inform how we categorize past activities. In a sophisticated version of Collingwood’s scissors-and-paste history: when something looks like science to us we assume it is and was science. Here the historian in the […]
[…] and, consequently, authority in historical matters (for more on historical expertise, see here, here, here, here and here). Indeed, his On the Shoulders of Giants is not a work of history but rather, […]
Adrian Wilson makes some useful points about Collingwood in the collection of essays he edited, Rethinking Social History: English Society 1570-1920 and its Interpretation (Manchester, 1993). He appropriates some points made by RGC and matches him up with Geoffrey Elton to hammer home the notion of concept-criticism, the endless quest for anachronism in which historians of science engage.
Adrian is particularly good on the problem of document criticism and source criticism.
One of the best critical analyses of Collingwood that I’ve seen, which includes discussion of where he might lead the unwary astray, is William H. Dray, History as Re-Enactment: R.G.Collingwood’s Idea of History (Oxford, 1995).
The author tackles some of the epistemological and ontological problems, as well as the metaphysical position that attempts to join them. Or not. He also considers Collingwood’s failure to recognize some of the most interesting historical questions, although I think much of the criticism is anachronistic — RGC could hardly be expected to anticipate all of our current interests.
[Surprised to see HK here.]
[…] illnesses in the past. These difficulties, however, seem to be no impediment for the determined “scissors-and-paste” researcher armed with a pair of sharp scissors and ready to excise choice quotations in an […]